Not everyone can be an expert in
biology, computer science, chemistry, electrical engineering, genetics,
kinesiology, medicine, physics,
psychiatry, whatever, or zoology (in alphabetical order), but we could all benefit
from a general grasp of various scientific ideologies, their epistemology's,
and philosophies. The published journals, papers (peer reviewed and otherwise), and general treatises which
record and recapitulate the progress of human thought concerning explanation
are open not only to those residing in Olympus, nor are they reserved for
academically trained readers, but such communications are for all of us. The works of Aristotle, Spinoza’s Ethics, and
even Wittgenstein’s Tractus are less readable now than when they were written. The Proceedings of the Royal Society’s
literature are as obtuse to many as when Pepys, Dryden, and Evelyn were
fellows. In consequence, there have
grown up two classes of writings that are needed more now than ever before, on which a
non-scientific reader has to rely on for wisdom, understanding, and
discernment. For any of us there are
works of popular science where theoretical advances are explained in a way
crafted to avoid technicalities; and for students of philosophy there are books
and articles on logic in which the nature and problems of some sciences are
discussed as deduction and induction based upon application of the scientific method.
Many of these books discuss first
the premise of logic, applications of set theory, number theory, grammar, causality, Boolean algebra, Lie algebra, Voronoi diagrams, Venn diagrams, algorithms,
calculus, statistics, and many other tools.
Whether the results of the sciences are true or only highly probable,
the uniformity of nature, the accumulation of confirming instances, Mill’s methods, and the probability-calculus form the basis of most laws, theories,
and expositions. But to anyone with
practical experience of science there is a curious, almost mystical, air of
unreality concerning the appearance of the results. Lucid, erudite, and carefully framed as the ideological structures might be yet somehow missing the universal mark of the
absolute. It is not that the statements
are untrue fallacies, but rather that they appear irrelevant when taken out of
context. The hypothesis (null and otherwise) that are impeccably written with
eloquent mathematics and rational discussion are often perceived as having no
application or bearing on everyday life.
Not since the discovery of fire has a scientific idea’s application and
conflagration been instantly apparent.
Meanwhile the actual methods of rhetoric employed are rarely
examined. For example, writers such as
Kuhn, Poincare, and Hickey recognize that one must not take too much for
granted. Several years before Einstein
developed his relativity theory the mathematician Poincare postulated a
non-Euclidean physical space and claimed that physicists had two choices. Either to accept non-Euclidean geometry as a
description of physical space or they can preserve Euclidean geometry for the
description of physical space by adopting new physical laws stating that all
solid bodies undergo certain contractions and expansions as later noted by
thermodynamics and other sciences, and that light does not travel in straight
lines. Poincare maintained that
physicists would always choose to preserve the Euclidean description of
physical space, and would claim that any observed non-Euclidean deviations are
due to the relative expansion or contraction of the instruments of measurement
and to the deflection of light rays, no matter how miniscule, yet
noticeable. Einstein’s choice of the Riemannian geometry and physical laws for measurement were based on the resulting
simplicity of the total system of established physics. Relativity theory using Riemannian geometry
greatly simplifies physical laws by the implementation of geodesics, such as
the gravitation as a force is replaced by gravitation as a function of
geometrical structure of curved space.
While many of us tend to assume some familiarity with the things that
thinkers, scientists, or celebrities say and do glossing over the details that
support the really intriguing philosophical points that follow.
This is an attitude that exposes
each of us to cognitive biases, logical fallacies, or other dangers. For if an individual has too simple an idea
of what constitutes a statement, proof, or argument then philosophical
inconsistencies occur that have no application other than humorous anecdotes ad absurdum. If we are to take for granted
that “opals and pearls are simply white” or that “Men do not require
instruction” it could be concluded that appealing to such laws rest on the
presupposition about the reliability of a subscription to gross generalization
weekly. But unless we are to see with
clarity what the laws of nature are in practice who can decide the accuracy and
precision of a proper conclusion? The
laws of nature cannot fit into the traditional array of logical categories with
their corresponding criteria, leading to specialization in discussion within
further refined sciences; ideological refining as an iterative and recursive
process that also requires interdisciplinary communication to ensure
compatibility, consistency, and validity for future applications. Similarly anyone can think about the
mechanics of causation and its place in modern sciences indefinitely, until it
is noticed just how rarely the word ‘cause’ is employed in the scholarly works
of professional researchers or scientists.
There is good reason for this rarity, a reason that if ignored is to
divide reality from the philosophical discussion of scientific arguments.
A student of philosophy benefits
from an introductory education of the types of arguments, proof, and methods
scientists employ in practice and how these are similar to those traditionally
applied by theologians, logicians, and other orators. To what degree are the examples in a logic
book congruent with the practice of scientists, and what are the implications
on the rest of us? Are we to deconstruct
these problems in a customary fashion and attempt to propound some novel
solution; or are we to view the problems themselves as arising from naiveté
conceptions that have existed since their inception. How are we to conclude that an explanation is
acceptable and therefore applicable?
What sort of impression must an expression perform to qualify on the
level of Newton’s Second Law of Thermodynamics, or as a law of nature? How does this differ from a proposed
hypothesis? Is the difference merely a
matter of degrees of a confidence interval in the classes of a proposition, or
is a distinction to drawn on other grounds?
And what role does mathematics play?
As for new entities in the sciences that are so often discussed: the
Higgs-Boson, patented genes and their genetic markers, Quantum-computing, or
what have you. Are those things thought
of as actually existing, and when are they explanatory devices? These are all questions whose answers are
easy to be mistaken about, unless we are to pay sufficient attention to the
actual practices of scientists. The rest
of this writing will examine the features which must be pondered in order to
settle some questions.
The difficulties that do arise
between understanding, educational entrainment, and most individuals
understanding on popular science are rather different. Within this facsimile of an authentic
scientific document there can be little to no doubt that what is discussed if
rather different. The cognates of
various ideas are not only discrete, but are also fair game along with
appearance, perception, cognition, behavior, communication, linguistics,
humanities, mathematics, anthropology, agriculture, architecture, every and all
other books, articles, and recapitulations on books of popular science that
might otherwise be defined as rather different.
As for me, and my point of view there is no doubt that authentic science
is simultaneously being discussed; but the terms by which these ideas are first
presented are not as discrete nor as explanatory as first they might seem to a
tailor. There is a tendency for those
philosophical writers within this field to explain to the readers only about
the models, conceptions, and formulations, employed in a novel theory instead
of first giving readers a firm anchor of facts of which the theories
explanations are based and afterword illustrating to the reader the method by
which the manner the theories fit the hierarchy of facts.
Recall, for instance, the means
by which Sir James Jeans and Sir Arthur Eddington took to spreading the non
popular belief and thought that the theories of Physics based upon Isaac Newton, Leibniz, Spinoza, Descartes, Poincare, Copernicus, Bacon, Feynman,
Einstein, Democritus, Socrates, Aristotle, Pythagoras, Sophocles, etc, etc,
et, all of physics, modern, post modern, and everything else that will come to
be. Because too often those philosopher
of science focused upon that which would otherwise be declared as comparatively
inessential, what is introduced to the reader as predefined conceptions,
particular models, or theories used to describe immanent phenomenon even when
failing to do that which is essential, namely to elucidate the measurable and
mathematical function of such adopted variable as they are derived into models,
theoretical conceptions and the rest.
The well known two tables account is an established case in point much
like an all you can eat buffet. For a reader to acquiesce to Eddington’s multiplex
understanding of ‘the two tables’ upon a surface that is understood as not only
a tabletop defined as a case in point
“common-sense, solid table top”, which is also a scientific table top
mostly consisting of empty space. This
recapitulation does not particularly assist a reader in the dubious task of what
defines an atomic model which is more important to the sciences of explaining
the chemical occurrences around us as it might be the atomic theory of
matter. The entirety of such models is
to explain that which could not other there unto be explained by traditional
models. Cut off from the phenomenon of the
model one can only be mislead, raising further unreal and needless conceptions
about what might happen when the tea-tray that supports it is set down. The same also goes regrettably for those
pretty pictures of electron clouds encompassing our mind of atoms like bees which
might hum about a blank center in a cathedral, the pictures of your brain as an
anagram of our universe, depictions of your white and gray matter as a network
of computers and their entwined connections, and rest. Regrettably in can be said, because we as literary
devices certainly have value, and if we were not left to stand on our own feet
we might have value, unfortunately that value is defined by the very limitations
of the language implemented to transfer such ideas via a written word. The same also goes for the written word which
acts as a searchlight in the darkness, picking up there a pinnacle, a chimney,
and in a distance an attic window; the detail illuminated is dazzlingly
commensurate even while everything surrounding is caste into even greater obscurity
until we are all distracted from the overall proportions with which we have
been beautifully presented.
This is not the worst of which happens when assaulted by the human nature of appearances, appurtenances, reality, awareness, and perception. At times an attempt to popularize a physical theory might even result in unpopularizing it, for one might ask if it is not reverse psychology if it does not work. As things are elucidation generally operates as a searchlight through the darkness of human knowledge. For instance blue Jeans relied on finding a happy analogy which would by itself bring home to its readers the chief features of Einstein’s general theory of relativity. And how did he invite them to think of our universe? As the three dimensional surface of a four dimensional balloon? As the lack of condensation of anti-matter on the domain wall of a spinor Bose-Einstein optical lattice? The mislead layperson who had been acculturated to use the word surface for two dimensional things alone, now found themselves instructed to visualize what had otherwise been contradictory. So it was no wonder that many who agreed to Jeans’ calling the universe a mysterious one; A spectrum of mystification balanced by the confusion idea of unnecessary nothing. There is no reason that the principles of the Theory of Relativity should not be explained in the terms of an ordinary reader who can make something of Einstein. Oddly enough, Einstein does this very well. But Jeans’ method defeated its own end. Via reduction Jean defeated method by deconstructing the subject and object into that which is too easy and to do with a simile, metaphor, and allegory what no literary device alone can do, to lead many readers to conclude that what you are reading is utterly incomprehensible, thus this should now be set aside as not for you, the reader. But then how ought you now know as such?
This might suggest that Jeans was merely careless, even if there was more to what than that. For the fact that such writing picked up upon
a point of writing which is redundant and is to the outsider is
self-contradictory points to something which the average person must be told
about the linguistics of speech as they might be applied to theories. For when a theory is developed all kinds of
phrases in ordinary life are devoid of meaning are given use, many familiar
terms acquire fresh meanings, and a variety of new terms are introduced to
serve the purpose of the theory. A
scientists, who learns their physics the hard way gradually becomes accustomed
to implementing the novel technical terms and the everyday sounding phrases
required to confer the source of condensation on a domain wall, or whatever
even when less than half aware of what is really happening; as some professors
born remark; the building
of the languages of the sciences is not entirely a conscious process. This has its consequence when a scientist has
to explain a new theory to the lay person.
For then it is possible to unwittingly use in exposition terms and turns
of phrase which can only be understood by those already familiar with the
theory. To the individual trained in the
implementation of sophisticated geometry the phrase “three-dimensional surface”
might no longer be a self-contradiction, but for those regurgitating it without
appreciation to a non-mathematician it is an invitation to
incomprehension. And what happens to
three dimensional surfaces like that which we live upon is equitable to
invisible light and their constituents.
When scientific notions are being popularized it is necessary to explain
the foci of such phrases, instead of making unexplained and untranslated use of
them.
To introduce a valued distinction
is now of value. For a communities
adoption of a new theory involves a linguistic shift that can be distinguished
between the account of the theory and the application of the new terminology in
a participant language sense which is an account in the new terminology by
which it is not used but is described by the voyeuristic nature of an onlooker’s
language. Supposing as Wittgenstein said
in his ‘Tractus’ that “A physicist tells you that at last the discovery of how
to see people in the dark, which no one had ever before known”. Then you should not be surprised. If Wittgenstein goes on to explain to you
that the discovery of brainwave entrainment by means of gravitational induction
is as ancient an idea as communication then you have a right to be surprised if
you feel like it. Then it is a different
kind of surprise, not just a mental whirl, because before such a statement one
may not just gape open after having been stretched but must ask: “What do you
mean?”
An analogy will help to explain
misconceptions that might follow if we were to attempt to popularize the physical
sciences in such a way. When children are told stories at bedtime they are told
about all kinds of people, not just rich and poor, white and black, beggars,
and kings, but the more encompassing logically different people. Some nights they are told stories from
history, other nights ancient myths, sometimes legends, sometimes fables,
sometimes they might even be accounts of we ourselves have done, other times
accounts by contemporary authors.
Therefore when it comes to bedtime stories, this, Caesar, Cleopatra, Scheherazade, Heraclitus, Democritus, Achilles, Sisyphus, the boy who cried wolf, the man in the yellow hat, and Winnie the Pooh all appear at first sight to be on the
same footing. A clever child, no doubt,
soon learns to spot from internal evidence what kind of story tonight's story
is, and what sort of people its characters are, fabulous, legendary or
historical, But to begin with we must
explain in asides what the logical status of each character and story is,
saying, “No there aren’t really any talking animals: this is just a made up
story”, or “yes, this really did happen, when my father was a boy.” Unless the child is told these things in
addition to the stories themselves, he might not know how to take them; and
thus he might bet quite false ideas about the world into which he was born,
about its history, its inhabitants, and the kinds of things he might encounter
on any day as he turns the corner on the street. If entertainment alone were needed, the story
alone might do. But the risks of
misunderstanding are serious, and for real understanding more is always a
requirement.
So in popular science: the
average person is not merely ignorant of all the theories of science but is
also unequipped to understand the terms in which a scientist will naturally
begin to explain them. To explain the
sciences to the average person by giving the intrepid reader only potted theories and vivid
analogies, without a good number of thoroughly confusing and logical asides, is
like telling a child all of the sorts of stories we do tell children and not warning
them as to the pitfalls, variations, and different inconsistencies
therein. Then no child will not know
what weights to put on the various things that are said, which of the
statements heard about the sciences are to be accepted at face value, and which
narratives are misleading preponderances that are never to be met.
Perhaps the nub of the difficulty
lies in that the popularizer has at least a double aim. For most people would like to learn about the
theories of the sciences in a language that is understandable; and most would
like to learn this as Stephan Hawking has translated the universe “in a nutshell”. These opposing ends of a
spectrum are bound together as part of the same thing which are in practice a
conflict. For a major virtue of the language
of the sciences is it conciseness. It is
always generally possible to say what a scientific theory amounts to without
using the technical terms which scientists introduce to serve the purposes of
the theory, although one can do so only by writing at very much greater
length. If the popularizer is to explain
a theory in everyday terms and at the same time put it “in a nutshell”,
something must first be sacrificed in terms of the technical accuracy of the
premise. Usually the logical asides are
the first thing to go, and drastic cuts follow in the account of the phenomenon
which the theory is introduced to explain.
What is even more important is just how much further along in the
development of the idea the reader is when presented with the ‘explanation’. As it is the reader might often be better off
if simply left in the dark as far as the matter is concerned, due only to the
simplification to the sharp point of Occam’s razor. Once this happens the
everyday public individual is given no real entrance to the subject; for until
they are told a good deal about the phenomena a real key is of little use if
the beholden is unaware of what rooms it grants access to. There is then no point to being told that
Einstein has discovered the metaphorical key to the universe if we are not also
informed as to what sort of thing counts as opening said door with said key.
However, something can be done to
remedy such a state of affairs. With the
help of a few elementary examples it should be possible to show the common
reader some of the more important ideas required regarding the logic of the
physical sciences. There is no reason
for anyone to rest content with the ideological nature of the sciences are an
inconsistent conglomeration of self-contradictions, like invisible
electromagnetic phenomenon, three dimensional surfaces, and mysteries like the
curvature of space. When armed with the
ability to ask questions all can penetrate behind the screen of appearance and
reality to the living truth. For the
words of scientists are not always what they seem, and might be misleading if
taken even slightly out of their original context. The vital information is what sorts of
questions should be asked if one is to garner a satisfactory understanding of a
given theory; fortunately this is something which can be shown well with
sophisticated and simple examples. To
illustrate what such questions are is the purpose of this writing you the
reader are now engaged in perusing. It
will not require that you are capable of quoting the exact words of scientists
so much as it necessitates the ability to notice the sort of things they do
with the words they do employ. As
Einstein has said: “If you want to find out anything from the theoretical
physicists about the methods they use, I advise you to stick closely to one
principle: don’t pay attention to their words, fix your attention on their
deeds.
This blog post is no different in aim, deed, or execution. In fact this is merely an experimental foray into the metalinguistics of pronouns, and their subsequent psycholinguistic effects. Thank you for your time, feedback, and complicit participation.
This blog post is no different in aim, deed, or execution. In fact this is merely an experimental foray into the metalinguistics of pronouns, and their subsequent psycholinguistic effects. Thank you for your time, feedback, and complicit participation.